The capabilities approach to health and social justice: moving from the individual/bio-medical or natural scientific level of causation to supra-individual/social or social scientific causal pathways
“…as it currently stands, the dominant explanatory model in
epidemiology is significantly constrained even in explaining diseases. It is
not able to explain fully the causation and distribution of diseases most
prevalent in developed economies, namely chronic and degenerative conditions.
The current paradigm is not providing satisfactory explanation for all the
observable facts of disease and its social distribution patterns. [….]
Three specific limitations of the prevailing model of
disease aetiology are often at the centre of debates about the ‘paradigm
crisis’ in epidemiology. These include its level of analysis, its inability to
recognize distribution patterns, and its partially informed recommendations for
policy. The current model, which evolved from the late-nineteenth-century germ
theory of disease, recognizes three categories of causal factors. These factors
include biological endowments, behaviours and external exposures to harmful
substances or ‘agents.’ The resulting limitation of this model is that it
operates only a single level, at the individual level, and expresses a form of
explanatory individualism. Short causal pathways confined to the human body are
studied, while the model precludes recognizing and supra-individual level factors
or social processes as part of the longer causal chain in the production of
disease. As a result, the model studies individuals in a vacuum and
disconnected from other individuals; it is only focused on what happens on and
within the skin of individuals.”
The significance of the “level” of causal analysis, in this
case, as “supra-individual level factors or social processes,” was in fact
appreciated in some quarters in the early nineteenth century. In doing research
for my latest bibliography on “philosophy, psychology and methodology for the social sciences,” I came across the following passage from Richard W. Miller’s
unduly neglected or under-appreciated work (inferred from the comparatively few
references found in the literature), Fact and Method: Explanation, Confirmation and Reality in the Natural and Social Sciences (Princeton University Press,
1987):
“In the organized pursuit of explanation, practical concerns
may…dictate choice of a standard causal pattern. In the early nineteenth
century, many investigators had come to explain the prevalence of certain
diseases in certain places as due to filth and overcrowding. For example, the
prevalence of tuberculosis in urban slums was understood this way. In these
explanations, the microbial agent was not, of course, described. But the causal
factors mentioned were actual causes of the prevalence of some of those
diseases. If Manchester had not been
filthy and overcrowded, tuberculosis would not have been prevalent. On the
purely scientific dimension, acceptance of accurate environmental explanations
probably did not encourage as many causal ascriptions as would a standard
requiring explanation of why some victims of filth and overcrowding became
tubercular, some not. Those who pressed the latter question were to lead the
great advances of the germ theory. But in
a practical way, the environmental explanations did a superior job, encouraging
more important causal accounts. Guided
by those accounts, sanitary measures produced dramatic reductions in
tuberculosis and other diseases, more dramatic, in fact, than the germ theory
has yielded. A perspicacious investigator might have argued, ‘We know that
some specific and varied accompaniment of filth and overcrowding is crucial,
since not every child in the Manchester slums is tubercular. But we should
accept explanations of the prevalence of disease which appeal to living
conditions. For they accurately, if vaguely, describe relevant causal factors,
and give us the means to control the prevalence of disease.” [emphasis added]
Incidentally, Paul Thagard’s fairly sophisticated model of
“disease explanation” as “causal network instantiation,” elaborated in his book
How Scientists Explain Disease
(Princeton University Press, 1999), includes a possible causal role for environmental
factors, but the concept and meaning of health as such is not addressed, the
implication being that disease is simply the converse of health (along with
illness or, socially speaking, sickness), namely, “ill-health” (understood as
an instance of a clinically identifiable biological pathology). As we will see
at a later date, Venkatapuram’s capabilities approach to health spells out a
normatively robust conception of health and well-being that is far more than
the mere converse of “ill-health,” however important that life condition
remains indicative of a significant social achievement.
0 Comments:
Post a Comment
<< Home